(Standard post on cardinals, as a prerequisite for forthcoming theory model post.)
An ordinal measures a total ordering. However, it does not do a fantastic job at measuring size. For example, there is a bijection between the elements of and
:
In fact, as you likely already know, there is even a bijection between and
:
So ordinals do not do a good job of keeping track of size. For this, we turn to the notion of a cardinal number.
1. Equinumerous Sets and Cardinals
Definition 1 Two sets
and
are equinumerous, written
, if there is a bijection between them.
Definition 2 A cardinal is an ordinal
such that for no
do we have
.
Example 3 (Examples of Cardinals) Every finite number is a cardinal. Moreover,
is a cardinal. However,
,
,
are not, because they are countable.
Example 4 (
is Countable) Even
is not a cardinal, since it is a countable union
and each
is countable.
Ques 5 Why must an infinite cardinal be a limit ordinal?
Remark 6 There is something fishy about the definition of a cardinal: it relies on an external function
. That is, to verify
is a cardinal I can’t just look at
itself; I need to examine the entire universe
to make sure there does not exist a bijection
for
. For now this is no issue, but later in model theory this will lead to some highly counterintuitive behavior.
2. Cardinalities
Now that we have defined a cardinal, we can discuss the size of a set by linking it to a cardinal.
Definition 7 The cardinality of a set
is the least ordinal
such that
. We denote it by
.
Ques 8 Why must
be a cardinal?
Remark 9 One needs the Well-Ordering Theorem (equivalently, Choice) in order to establish that such an ordinal
actually exists.
Since cardinals are ordinals, it makes sense to ask whether , and so on. Our usual intuition works well here.
Proposition 10 (Restatement of Cardinality Properties) Let
and
be sets.
if and only
, if and only if there is a bijection between
and
.
if and only if there is an injective map
.
Ques 11 Prove this.
3. Aleph Numbers
Prototypical example for this section: is
, and
is the first uncountable
First, let us check that cardinals can get arbitrarily large:
Proposition 12 We have
for every set
.
Proof: There is an injective map but there is no injective map
by Cantor’s diagonal argument.
Thus we can define:
Definition 13 For a cardinal
, we define
to be the least cardinal above
, called the successor cardinal.
This exists and has
.
Next, we claim that:
Exercise 14 Show that if
is a set of cardinals, then
is a cardinal.
Thus by transfinite induction we obtain that:
Definition 15 For any
, we define the aleph numbers as
Thus we have the following sequence of cardinals:
By definition, is the cardinality of the natural numbers,
is the first uncountable ordinal, \dots.
We claim the aleph numbers constitute all the cardinals:
Lemma 16 (Aleph Numbers Constitute All Infinite Cardinals) If
is a cardinal then either
is finite (i.e.
) or
for some
.
Proof: Assume is infinite, and take
minimal with
. Suppose for contradiction that we have
. We may assume
, since the case
is trivial.
If is a successor, then
which contradicts the fact the definition of the successor cardinal. If is a limit ordinal, then
is the supremum
. So there must be some
has
, which contradicts the minimality of
.
Definition 17 An infinite cardinal which is not a successor cardinal is called a limit cardinal. It is exactly those cardinals of the form
, for
a limit ordinal, plus
.
4. Cardinal Arithmetic
Prototypical example for this section:
Recall the way we set up ordinal arithmetic. Note that in particular, and
. Since cardinals count size, this property is undesirable, and we want to have
because and
are countable. In the case of cardinals, we simply “ignore order”.
The definition of cardinal arithmetic is as expected:
Definition 18 (Cardinal Arithmetic) Given cardinals
and
, define
and
Ques 19 Check this agrees with what you learned in pre-school for finite cardinals.
This is a slight abuse of notation since we are using the same symbols as for ordinal arithmetic, even though the results are different ( but
). In general, I’ll make it abundantly clear whether I am talking about cardinal arithmetic or ordinal arithmetic. To help combat this confusion, we use separate symbols for ordinals and cardinals. Specifically,
will always refer to
viewed as an ordinal;
will always refer to the same set viewed as a cardinal. More generally,
Definition 20 Let
viewed as an ordinal.
However, as we’ve seen already we have that . In fact, this holds even more generally:
Theorem 21 (Infinite Cardinals Squared) Let
be an infinite cardinal. Then
.
Proof: Obviously , so we want to show
.
The idea is to repeat the same proof that we had for , so we re-iterate it here. We took the “square” of elements of
, and then re-ordered it according to the diagonal:
Let’s copy this idea for a general .
We proceed by transfinite induction on . The base case is
, done above. For the inductive step, first we put the “diagonal” ordering
on
as follows: for
and
in
we declare
if
(they are on different diagonals), or
and
(same diagonal).
Then is a well-ordering of
, so we know it is in order-preserving bijection with some ordinal
. Our goal is to show that
. To do so, it suffices to prove that for any
, we have
.
Suppose corresponds to the point
under this bijection. If
and
are both finite, then certainly
is finite too. Otherwise, let
; then the number of points below
is at most
by the inductive hypothesis. So as desired.
From this it follows that cardinal addition and multiplication is really boring:
Theorem 22 (Infinite Cardinal Arithmetic is Trivial) Given cardinals
and
, one of which is infinite, we have
Proof: The point is that both of these are less than the square of the maximum. Writing out the details:
5. Cardinal Exponentiation
Prototypical example for this section: .
Definition 23 Suppose
and
are cardinals. Then
Here
is the set of functions from
to
.
As before, we are using the same notation for both cardinal and ordinal arithmetic. Sorry!
In particular, , and so from now on we can use the notation
freely. (Note that this is totally different from ordinal arithmetic; there we had
. In cardinal arithmetic
.)
I have unfortunately not told you what equals. A natural conjecture is that
; this is called the Continuum Hypothesis. It turns out to that this is undecidable — it is not possible to prove or disprove this from the
axioms.
6. Cofinality
Prototypical example for this section: ,
, \dots are all regular, but
has cofinality
.
Definition 24 Let
be a limit ordinal, and
another ordinal. A map
of ordinals is called cofinal if for every
, there is some
such that
. In other words, the map reaches arbitrarily high into
.
Example 25 (Example of a Cofinal Map)
- The map
by
is cofinal.
- For any ordinal
, the identity map
is cofinal.
Definition 26 Let
be a limit ordinal. The cofinality of
, denoted
, is the smallest ordinal
such that there is a cofinal map
.
Ques 27 Why must
be an infinite cardinal?
Usually, we are interested in taking the cofinality of a cardinal .
Pictorially, you can imagine standing at the bottom of the universe and looking up the chain of ordinals to . You have a machine gun and are firing bullets upwards, and you want to get arbitrarily high but less than
. The cofinality is then the number of bullets you need to do this.
We now observe that “most” of the time, the cofinality of a cardinal is itself. Such a cardinal is called regular.
Example 28 (
is Regular)
, because no finite subset of
can reach arbitrarily high.
Example 29 (
is Regular)
. Indeed, assume for contradiction that some countable set of ordinals
reaches arbitrarily high inside
. Then
is a countable ordinal, because it is a countable union of countable ordinals. In other words
. But
is an upper bound for
, contradiction.
On the other hand, there are cardinals which are not regular; since these are the “rare” cases we call them singular.
Example 30 (
is Not Regular) Notice that
reaches arbitrarily high in
, despite only having
terms. It follows that
.
We now confirm a suspicion you may have:
Theorem 31 (Successor Cardinals Are Regular) If
is a successor cardinal, then it is regular.
Proof: We copy the proof that was regular.
Assume for contradiction that for some , there are
sets reaching arbitrarily high in
as a cardinal. Observe that each of these sets must have cardinality at most
. We take the union of all
sets, which gives an ordinal
serving as an upper bound.
The number of elements in the union is at most
and hence .
7. Inaccessible Cardinals
So, what about limit cardinals? It seems to be that most of them are singular: if is a limit ordinal, then the sequence
(of length
) is certainly cofinal.
Example 32 (Beth Fixed Point) Consider the monstrous cardinal
This might look frighteningly huge, as
, but its cofinality is
as it is the limit of the sequence
More generally, one can in fact prove that
But it is actually conceivable that is so large that
.
A regular limit cardinal other than has a special name: it is weakly inaccessible. Such cardinals are so large that it is impossible to prove or disprove their existence in
. It is the first of many so-called “large cardinals”.
An infinite cardinal is a strong limit cardinal if
for any cardinal . For example,
is a strong limit cardinal.
Ques 33 Why must strong limit cardinals actually be limit cardinals? (This is offensively easy.)
A regular strong limit cardinal other than is called strongly inaccessible.
8. Exercises
Problem 1 Compute
.
Problem 2 Prove that for any limit ordinal
,
is a regular cardinal.
Sproblem 3 (Strongly Inaccessible Cardinals) Show that for any strongly inaccessible
, we have
.
Problem 4 (Konig’s Theorem) Show that
for every infinite cardinal
.
(This post is a draft of a chapter from my Napkin project.)